• About
  • Books

memoirandremains

memoirandremains

Tag Archives: epistemology

A theology of sensory perception (very rough draft)

09 Saturday Apr 2022

Posted by memoirandremains in Psychology, Theology of Biblical Counseling

≈ 2 Comments

Tags

epistemology, Sensory Perceptioin, Theology of Psychology

(I am posting this very rough draft essay for the purpose of soliciting comments, if anyone would be so kind. Please know that even complete disagreement will be welcome. This is an essay in a series which I am working on to make a theological review of psychology as a discipline. (I have posted three prior essays on this topic; which all have been published in the Journal of Biblical Soul Care.) This essay concerns the question of sensory perception (as the first step in a theory of knowledge). It is extremely rough. Transitions are missing, there is some repetition, citations are not in proper format et cetera. Anyway, if you are so inclined, a critique would be appreciated. I will provide a link to the completed version when it is published.)

Teasdale: Your Excellency, I thought you left.

Chicolini: Oh no. I no leave.

Teasdale: But I saw you with my own eyes.

Chicolini: Well, who ya gonna believe me or your own eyes?

            -Duck Soup[1]

Introduction:

Biblical Soul Care (“BSC”) aces the charge it is “unscientific,” as opposed to  “psychology” (that notoriously broad term) which is a “science.”  While philosophically sophisticated definitions will provide far more nuance, such nuance is not the issue when BSC is said to be “unscientific.”  Something which is “scientific” is true.  Something “unscientific” might be “nice for you,” but it is certainly a substandard sort of knowledge.

Another thing about “scientific” knowledge (I’m going to stop putting quotation marks around “science” and “scientific”) is that it is neutral knowledge: it information which is true for everyone.  The function of gravity is identical in a Buddhist Temple and a university lecture room. .

Unscientific knowledge, like BSC, is a sort of preference, a sort of biased knowledge. But we can expand the problem with BSC to theological claims generally. Theological claims are not “true” in any hard sense of the term. They are just things people believe “without evidence.”

There is no need to belabor this point: it is a commonplace of our culture: it is a given which is simply true. Only a benighted “fundamentalist” would possibly conclude anything different.

What then is the bedrock which gives science such an unassailable claim to truth? First, science is based upon empirical observations. We have access to sense impressions which are self-authenticating and unquestionably true presentations of the world. (In fact, even our conscious awareness of sense impressions is itself an empirical fact, and thus self-authenticating.).

Second, by use of rational inquiry, one can logically understand the world in an objectively true manner.

Those twin claims make science true. Since theology is not merely examining sense impressions by means of rational inquiry it cannot be “true,” like other knowledge is true.

My goal in this essay is to undermine the first prong of this “scientism” claim: that sense impressions are self-authenticating.  This does not mean that I wish to conclude the physical world is an illusion–far from it. My concern is with the justification, the warrant for the belief that sense impressions are objectively true.

Sense impressions, as you will learn, result from a remarkable, strange process: a process which in-and-of itself cannot itself justify the content of any sense impression as being “true.” Sense impressions can only be justified as true on the basis of an assertion which cannot be grounded in the sense impressions.

Only a theological presupposition can justify sense impressions as being “true.”  And so, rather than theological claims being half-witted step-children of rational inquiry, theological claims are the only thing which makes any rational inquiry possible.

I am going to begin with first asserting the nature of “psychology’s” claim to scientific knowledge about the nature of human knowledge.  Having situated that assertion on the basis of sense impression, I will then proceed to demonstrate the manner in which sense impressions bear an arbitrary and unjustified correlation to the “real world.”

In a way, I am going to ask you to believe me, rather than your lying eyes.

Psychology’s Claim to Knowledge About Knowledge

Psychology[2] occupies a unique place among academic disciplines. All disciplines whether science or humanity state a claim to knowledge. Roman history is a claim to knowledge concerning Rome. Physics is a claim to knowledge concerning “matter and energy and the effect that each has on the other.”[3] 

Psychology claims to have certain knowledge about the internal “psychological” functioning of human beings.  In that respect, psychology is similar to other disciplines. Thus, a psychologist who studies the effectiveness of various teaching techniques would have knowledge about that teaching techniques.

But psychology, or at least certain subdisciplines of psychology claim to possess knowledge about how we know. Such a psychologist would claim to have knowledge about how the physicist can understand matter and energy – not about the experiments or observations of the physicist, but rather how the physicist as a human being can acquire knowledge.

For most of human history, the examination of how we know, epistemology, was the work of philosophers. And as such, the various positions were up for debate. One could hold to Plato or Kant. But something has happened with psychology’s entry into the field. Rather merely positing a philosophy of knowledge, psychology claims to assert a scientific knowledge of knowledge itself.

The Word “Science”

The word “science” has a peculiar place in our rhetoric. By asserting something is “science,” we mean that it is an unassailable truth; it is an objective determination which must be acceded to by all reasonable people.

At this point, I need to take an aside note the difficult of discussing “science” at this moment in time.  There is a rational contention well-grounded in Christian thought that the world is there, is comprehensible, and follows regular patterns laid down by God. We would call these “laws of nature.”

Eventually, the predominate position of those who examine such things became since there are laws in nature, there is no need to conclude there is a God of nature. (This is a wholly unwarranted position, but is not my concern at the moment.) That position that there is an objective world which follows laws which can be observed and largely understood is in a general matter a presupposition for science.

This understanding reached its highwater mark when it was enshrined as federal law. In case which considered whether Intelligent Design could be taught as science, the court held that “science” is a field of knowledge which specifically excludes God from consideration:

Expert testimony reveals that since the scientific revolution of the 16th and 17th centuries, science has been limited to the search for natural causes to explain natural phenomena. (9:19-22 (Haught); 5:25-29 (Pennock); 1:62 (Miller)). This revolution entailed the rejection of the appeal to authority, and by extension, revelation, in favor of empirical evidence. (5:28 (Pennock)). Since that time period, science has been a discipline in which testability, rather than any ecclesiastical authority or philosophical coherence, has been the measure of a scientific idea’s worth. (9:21-22 (Haught); 1:63 (Miller)). In deliberately omitting theological or “ultimate” explanations for the existence or characteristics of the natural world, science does not consider issues of “meaning” and “purpose” in the world. (9:21 (Haught); 1:64, 87 (Miller)). While supernatural explanations may be important and have merit, they are not part of science. (3:103 (Miller); 9:19-20 (Haught)). This self-imposed convention of science, which limits inquiry to testable, natural explanations about the natural world, is referred to by philosophers as “methodological naturalism” and is sometimes known as the scientific method. (5:23, 29-30 (Pennock)). Methodological naturalism is a “ground rule” of science today which requires scientists to seek explanations in the world around us based upon what we can observe, test, replicate, and verify. (1:59-64, 2:41-43 (Miller); 5:8, 23-30 (Pennock)). 

As the National Academy of Sciences (hereinafter “NAS”) was recognized by experts for both parties as the “most prestigious” scientific association in this country, we will accordingly cite to its opinion where appropriate. (1:94, 160-61 (Miller); 14:72 (Alters); 37:31 (Minnich)). NAS is in agreement that science is limited to empirical, observable and ultimately testable data: “Science is a particular way of knowing about the world. In science, explanations are restricted to those that can be inferred from the confirmable data — the results obtained through observations and experiments that can be substantiated by other scientists. Anything that can be observed or measured is amenable to scientific investigation. Explanations that cannot be based upon empirical evidence are not part of science.” (P-649 at 27).

Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District (M.D. Pa. 2005) 400 F. Supp. 2d 707, 735-36.  I say highwater, because shortly after this extreme form of  “science”  has come under attack from various directions.

From one direction, science is being attacked on racist and oppressive.

A math education professor in New York City claimed that the equation 2+2=4 “reeks of white supremacist patriarchy.”[4]

From another direction, “science” is being asserted as an unassailable truth for political reasons. Such as statement that a man who believes he is a woman is scientifically a woman[5]. Or the assertion that one must “follow the science” as a rhetorical stratagem to deny debate over continuous political issues. We will have reason to consider the nature of “science” in later essays.

For purposes of this essay, I will limit my examination of “science” largely to the definition of Kitzmiller and the “scientism” as explained by J.P. Moreland:

In scientism, therefore, science is the very paradigm of truth and rationality. Strong scientism implies that something is true, rationally justified, or known if and only if it is a scientific claim that has been success fully tested and that is being used according to appropriate scientific methodology. There are no truths that can be known apart from appropriately certified scientific claims, especially those in the hard or natural sciences.[6]

What this means is that if psychology is making a scientific-claims to understand human knowledge, psychology is in a position to exclude from consideration all things which “psychology” deems unscientific. Holding a position to “scientific” knowledge of knowing is a powerful place. As will be shown below, the claim to a self-authenticating “scientific” knowledge cannot be sustained, because at it most basic level, the matter of sense perception is itself not self-authenticating.

Epistemology as a Subdomain of Psychology

Willard Van Orman Quine[7], one of the preeminent philosophers of logic in the 20th Century, went so far as to sound as if the entire field of epistemology were merely an aspect of psychology:

Epistemology, or something like it, simply falls into place as a chapter of psychology and hence of natural science. It studies a natural phenomenon, viz., a physical human subject. This human subject is accorded a certain experimentally controlled input—certain patterns of irradiation in assorted frequencies, for instance—and in the fullness of time the subject delivers as output a description of the three-dimensional external world and its history. The relation between the meager input and the torrential output is a relation that we are prompted to study for somewhat the same reasons that always prompted epistemology; namely, in order to see how evidence related to theory, and in what ways one’s theory of nature transcends any available evidence.[8]

In this sense, psychology has a peculiar relationship to knowledge. But there is more. Again, I wish to emphasis what a profound shift is made by claiming to scientific knowledge as the basis of epistemology.

The great schools of epistemology gathered around Descartes or Plato or Locke or Kant all base their claim on the strength of philosophical inquiry. But the psychologist claims to “science,” a supposed disinterested and objective understanding of the world. A philosopher may have a “belief,” while science has certain objective knowledge.

The Problem Presented for Theological Inquiry

This presents an interesting problem for the theologian looking at psychology. Theology has moved to a subdomain of philosophy (at best) among the broader academic world, and can argue at best for “faith,” a private arena of opinion which may solace one but has no purchase in the “public square.” While “science” is a kind of knowledge which cannot be denied by any reasonable human being. In fact, to merely charge someone as rejecting science is sufficient to end the argument.

And so from a “respectable” position, my undertaking here seems a fools errand, or at something centuries out-of-date.

But I do not believe that it is true. As we will see, there is a fundamental difficulty which lies at the heart of this sure objective knowledge. In fact. it is by examining the peculiar nature of our senses – as our senses are understood by rational scientific inquiry – that makes the entire edifice of self-attesting science suspect.

The rhetorical trick of asserting “science” is in fact that: a rhetorical move, but neither an argument nor evidence.

But as we shall see, psychology’s claim to knowledge is far from simple or certain. Its claim to scientific certain is undercut by that same science which gives rise to its claims. Moreover, the questions of knowledge cannot be resolved with resort to philosophy and theology. 

In summary: the work of senses does not give us a reliable basis upon which to be certain about the world. I am not saying there is some defect in our sense. But what I am saying is that sensory apparatus is not self-authenticating. We have no reason to trust our senses if the only ground of that trust is the senses themselves. (And this becomes quite strange when we realize that what we know about our senses comes from our senses).

If we are to ground a belief in the reliability of our senses and the reality of the objective world, we will not find an adequate ground in the production of neurotransmitters (and the production of neurotransmitters is all our senses do.

The Overall Project

While we will begin in this essay with a consideration of our senses and the production of sense impressions, that is not the totality of our knowledge.  To fully understand the production of knowledge, we will need to carve up the question of knowledge into a series of issues.

First, there is the initial question of how do we apprehend the environment? Second, there is the organization of that information into cognizable units. Third, we must address the issue of brain and mind. Fourth, we come to the level of meaning. The question of meaning will entail a number of separate questions. We must consider emotion and cognition. We must consider certainty of that knowledge.

Fifth we come to question which lies within psychology subject matter: Rather than just learning about physical objects as is done by a physicist or a chemist, the psychology claims a knowledge of the unobservable psychological state of another human being.

What do we mean by “facts”?

Having said that psychology claims to a certainty of knowledge as a science entails a particular sort of claim.  By claiming to be a science, psychology claims to possess facts about the world and also to propose connections and organizing theories concern the world based upon those facts.

The facts are obtained by means of observation. Sense data is obtained and categorized. Through a process of laborious induction (repeated observations), certain patterns are perceived, such as rain only falls when there are clouds in the sky; or, my skin feels warmer when the sun shines on it.

A theory of some sort is proposed which explains “why” rain is tied to clouds or sunlight is tied to heat. That proposal is then tested. If the proposal after testing continues to make sense we have an arrangement of information which we call science[9].

Without question, psychology, like all science, rests upon an essentially empiricist foundation:

Empiricism

In philosophy generally, empiricism is a theory of knowledge emphasizing the role of experience.

In the philosophy of science, empiricism is a theory of knowledge which emphasizes those aspects of scientific knowledge that are closely related to experience, especially as formed through deliberate experimental arrangements.

It is a fundamental requirement of scientific method that all hypotheses and theories must be tested against observations of the natural world, rather than resting solely on a priori reasoning, intuition, or revelation.

Hence, science is considered to be methodologically empirical in nature.

https://www.sciencedaily.com/terms/empiricism.htm

And while there are variations among particular schools and particular psychologists (for instance, someone like Jung strays rather far afield from the narrower understanding of “science”), unstated givens for the work run along the lines of Locke through Hume. The world is understood on the basis of induction generated from sense data. A conclusion is then confirmed by the “scientific method”.[10]

The rock bottom of this whole process is the certainty that our sensory apparatus provides us a sure access the world. Science is built upon the bedrock of this sense data. Locke, who provides us with the philosophical starting point of empiricism takes the sense data as the given for his analysis:

My purpose, therefore, is to enquire into the origin, certainty, and extent of human knowledge, and also into the grounds and degrees of belief, opinion, and assent. I shan’t involve myself with the biological aspects of the mind. For example, I shan’t wrestle with the question of what alterations of our bodies lead to our having sensation through our sense-organs or to our having any ideas in our understandings. Challenging and entertaining as these questions may be, I shall by-pass them because they aren’t relevant to my project. All we need for my purposes is to consider the human ability to think.

Book I, Chapter 1, paragraph 2. David Hume furthers this sentiment as follows:

In short, all the materials of thinking are derived either from our outward or inward sentiment: The mixture and composition of these belongs alone to the mind and will. Or, to express myself in philosophical language, all our ideas or more feeble perceptions are copies of our impressions or more lively ones.

 p. 13 (see below for cite)  It is the common accessibility of this sense data to all persons which provides a basis for taking this information as “objective.”

It is at this point of sense data, that the agnostic and the atheist reject the notion of God as at best an inference to explain the relationship between various facts and thus as bad science dismissed as ‘faith’ – a sort of lessor knowledge.  It is the inability to gain direct knowledge of God’s person through our senses in the way that I gain knowledge of rabbits and rocks that makes God a disputable proposition. (This argument lies at the heart of the Kitzmiller decision above: since I can’t probe God the way I probe a sea cucumber, God is not “real” or least not objectively knowable.)

And so, at the level of sensory perception we have a claim to certain knowledge and a basis upon which we (humans) reject the existence of God[11].

Psychology, laying claim to domain expertise at this very point, thus raises some profoundly theological considerations which we pass by at our peril.

THE PHYSIOLOGY OF SENSORY PERCEPTION

Our naïve understanding of sight may run along the lines of manner in which a film camera. Film works because certain substances undergo an effectively permanent chemical response based upon exposure to light:

The imaging layers contain sub-micron sized grains of silver-halide crystals that act as the photon detectors. These crystals are the heart of photographic film. They undergo a photochemical reaction when they are exposed to various forms of electromagnetic radiation — light. In addition to visible light, the silver-halide grains can be sensitized to infrared radiation[12].

The pattern on the film forms an analog to the pattern of light which strikes the film. Light strikes an object, is bounced from the object to the film and on the film it makes a pattern which corresponds to the pattern and to the color (if color film) of the original. To use a tangible analogy, film works like a seal pressed into wax: one substance repeats the pattern in another substance.

The intuitive understanding of sight, and certainly an earlier understanding of sight, was that the eye simply bears the impress of the world around it.

However, a better analogy to understand sight is that it functions like digital photograph. There is in fact a correspondence between the perception and the world, but that correspondence is by means of a fundamental transformation.  Texas Tech University provides a useful description of the functionality of digital photography:

The CCD is a collection of tiny light-sensitive diodes, which convert photons (light) into electrons (electrical charge). These diodes are called photosites. In a nutshell, photons are converted to electron by the photosite and the electron is converted to voltage. Then, these analog forms (voltage) are digitized into pixels within the supporting camera circuitry before downloading to memory.

The importance here is that the original information is transformed from one form into a completely different structure. The pattern of light registered by the diodes is transformed in a collection of numbers: the information is digitized. The pattern created by the original impress of the light is gone having been translated into an entirely new (although correspondent) form of information[13].

This is essentially the mechanism by which our senses function: information from the environment is registered and then translated.

A detailed discussion of the physiology of sight would exceed our present needs. However, the general outline of the procedure will be of help. And so at the expense of simplifying this intricate process, and with all due apology, I will proceed:

First, there is the matter of bottom-up processing. This is the input of information from the environment. When light has passed through the lens of the eye, it lands on the retina:

The retina is a thin, delicate, transparent sheet of tissue derived from neuroectoderm. It comprises the sensory neurons that begin the visual pathway. The neural retina (neuroretina) is divided into nine layers: layer of inner and outer segments of the photoreceptors (rods and cones), external limiting membrane, outer nuclear layer, outer plexiform layer, inner nuclear layer, inner plexiform layer, ganglion cell layer, nerve fiber layer, and internal limiting membrane….Light must traverse these many layers before initiating signal transduction in the rods and cones[14].

If we consider this a bit more, we discover: “First is the fact that photons are discrete and are absorbed entirely, at which point they disappear.”[15] (A photon is a “particle” of light.) How exactly does the photon “disappear”?

 A single photon can interact with a long photosensitive molecule called retinal and quantum mechanics says that there is a certain quantum amplitude (a complex number whose length squared determines the probability of an event) for the photon to be absorbed, in which case the molecule changes it shape (called “photoisomerization”), which in turn triggers a powerful chemical amplification mechanism that makes the brain eventually aware of the photon being absorbed[16].

The photosensitive cells are known as “rods” and “cones”:

The retina contains two types of photoreceptors, rods and cones. The rods are more numerous, some 120 million, and are more sensitive than the cones. However, they are not sensitive to color. The 6 to 7 million cones provide the eye’s color sensitivity and they are much more concentrated in the central yellow spot known as the macula. In the center of that region is the ” fovea centralis “, a 0.3 mm diameter rod-free area with very thin, densely packed cones[17].

These photosensitive rods and cones are neurons. A primary function of a neuron is to receive a message and/or send a message, a signal. When then rod or cones is struck a photon it immediately passes on that information in a manner “just like any other neurons.[18]”  Thus, information is transferred by means of neurotransmitters. But the rods and cones are not the only type of cells on the retina. Moreover, there is an interaction among the cells to convey information. While you do not need to fully understand the mechanics, even a glimpse of the complexity at this space may help to understand all that follows:

The dichotomy between ON and OFF responses is a central one in the early stages of vision.  About half of the cells in the early visual system respond to light by increasing their rate of firing and half by decreasing it.  One may imagine the situation as being a push-pull one.  Retinal ganglion cells have fairly restricted rates of firing.  Their operating range is from around 0 to around 1,000 Hz.  The cells that are inhibited by light (OFF cells) tend to have a higher level of spontaneous activity in the dark.  They fire steadily even in the absence of a stimulus.  This means that they have a working range at “negative” rates of firing–rates below their resting rate.  One interpretation is that the overall range of signaling is thus expanded by having cells that work in two directions.

Another way to think about it is to consider the situation at an edge between a light and a dark zone.  What the visual system really cares about is transitions between light and dark.  Uniform areas of illumination carry little information; it is the points of change where information if contained.  If one has a light-dark edge, is the information contained in the lightness or the darkness?  It’s a glass that might be half empty or half full.  Information is contained in both lightness and darkness and the visual system respects each equally[19].

And so the information generated by means of the various combinations of cells on the retina interacting with the light send a series of messages down the optic nerve and to the thalamus, in particular to the Lateral Geniculate Nucleus, commonly referred to as the LGN. From there, information will eventually make its way to the visual cortex at the back of the brain. A visual representation of the processing channel looks like this[20]:

Diagram

Description automatically generated

The information processed by the LGN then is sent back to the visual cortex where it is processed as “sight”.  Now questions about “who” is seeing this, or how anything is “seen” will wait until a later essay. But this stage in our perception is not as “bottom-up processing.”

 “Bottom-up processing” (top down comes next) is the reception of some information from our environment which is observed by our senses by means of some sort of neurological response (a photon hits the retina, a sound wave hits the ear drum, and so one). The thing which is in the environment sets off a neurological cascade. One neuron informs another neuron and so on of the fact that a photon struck a particular place on the retina. The photon is not processed by the brain. The photon is no different than flipping a switch to turn on a light or a fan.

The initial reception of the environment is turned into an electro-chemical message. There is a complete translation of the environment into a format which can be processed by our brain.

And so we have considered a single aspect of our sensory perception: What we know is that the thing itself, but rather a translation of photons into a message conveyed by neurotransmitters. At this point, the question will become more complex – and in a strange way, less “real.”

Top-Down Processing

Now something quite interesting happens at this point. The LGN does not merely receive information from the retina. Information also comes in from other parts of the brain.  A schematic of the information appears as follows:[21]

Diagram

Description automatically generated

What I want you to see from this slide is that information concerning the object observed does not come solely from the light striking the retina. There is information coming from the visual cortex as well as the brain stem:

The axons of ganglion cells exit the retina to form the optic nerve, which travels to two places: the thalamus (specifically, the lateral geniculate nucleus, or LGN) and the superior colliculus. The LGN is the main relay for visual information from the retina to reach the cortex. Despite this, the retina only makes up about 20% of all inputs to the LGN, with the rest coming from the brainstem and the cortex. So more than simply acting as a basic relay for visual input from retina to cortex, the LGN is actually the first part of our visual pathway that can be modified by mental states.[22]

The creation of the image which is perceived is not simply a matter of taking in data from a photosensor, as in a digital photograph. Yes, there is the analogy to the digital photograph, but there is something more. Your brain does not merely translate photons into an array of neurotransmitters, it also constructs the image in something called “top-down processing.”

Below is a more technical explanation of what takes places in top-down processing. In in the simplest possible terms, our perceptions are not merely an imprint of the world (like film); nor is our perception simply a digital version of the world (like a digital camer). Rather, our perception is partially the result of information from the outside, but it is also the result of a construction imposed by brain based upon information outside the data from our senses: this information could be prior experience (for instance). What you need to understand is that our perception of the world is a matter of construction based upon current and prior experience of the world. Here is the more technical summary:

The functional properties of cortical neurons are not fixed. Rather, they can be thought of as adaptive processors, changing their function according to the behavioral context, and their responses reflect the demands of the perceptual task being performed. Cortical neurons are subject to top-down influences of attention, expectation and perceptual task. “Top-down” refers to cognitive influences and higher order representations that impinge upon earlier steps in information processing. Such influences represent a reversal of the central dogma of sensory information processing, which is based on feedforward connections along a hierarchy of cortical areas representing progressively more complex aspects of the visual scene. But superimposed on the feedforward pathways there are reentrant or feedback pathways that convey higher order information to antecedent cortical areas. The top-down signal carries a rich amount of information that facilitates the interpretation of the visual scene and that enables the visual system to build a stable representation of the objects within it, despite rapid and continuous eye movements. It facilitates our ability to segment the complex arrangement of multiple objects and backgrounds in the visual scene. In addition, the top-down signal plays a role in the encoding and recall of learned information. The resulting feedforward signals carried by neurons convey different meanings about the same visual scene according to the behavioral context. This idea is in stark contrast with the classical notion of a hierarchy of visual cortical areas — where information is conveyed in a feedforward fashion to progressively higher levels in the hierarchy, beginning with the analysis of simple attributes such as contrast and orientation, and leading to more complex functional properties from one stage to the next — and implies that vision is an active process. As we analyze visual scenes we set up countercurrent streams of processing, with the resulting percept reflecting the set of functional states of all the areas in the visual cortical hierarchy. In this review we consider the receptive field properties that are subject to top-down influences, the nature of the information that is conveyed by reentrant pathways, and how the information carried by neurons depends on behavioral context. Over longer time periods receptive fields can change to accommodate alterations in visual experience. These lines of evidence point towards an evolving view of the nature of the receptive field, which includes contextual influences and emphasizes its dynamic nature, with neurons taking on different properties in response to experience and expectation.[23]

What this means is that what we experience as sense perception is not simply looking out at the world and seeing what is there.

Over the course of time, we take in information from the world about us through our sense organs. That information is correlated in various was to build up a useful understanding of the world. This aspect of our understanding was developed most famously by Jean Piaget.  It is not necessary to conclude that Piaget’s explanation of the development of objects, space, and causality in the child are correct at all points to find the overall thrust of his understanding to be correct.

In the Introduction to his The Construction of Reality in the Child, that Piaget during the first two years of life, the child

At first directly assimilating the external environment of his own activity, later, in order ot extend this assimilation, forms an increasing number of schemata which are both more mobile and better able to coordinate. [Italics added]

Side by side with this progressive involvement of the assimilatory schemata runs the continuous elaboration of the external universe, in other words, the convergent development of explanatory function.

Jean Piaget, The Construction of Reality in the Child, trans. Margaret Cook (New York: Basic Books, 1954), p. xi. That is, the child develops mechanisms to understand the world about him. It is not that the child opens up his eyes and sees a world of permanent objects situated in space and time operating upon one-another by means of cause and effect. Instead, those concepts of external objects situated in space and time interacting by means of cause and effect are schemata the child develops and uses to understand the world. The remainder of the book is the detail on how such schemata are developed.

It is perhaps interesting to note that Kant held that the concepts of space and time are impositions of our mind; and that Hume held that causality was also an imposition upon reality by our mind. But a further analysis of the philosophers is beyond our instant concern.

What does matter is that our understanding of the world about us is not simply seeing “what is there.” Instead, while we begin with information from the world about us, we are also constructing that world by means of schemata.

The way in which such schemata function was illustrated by use finding an image from an obscure original:

To illustrate the basic idea of  why top-down processing is needed, researchers have created binarized photographs. In such photographs, gray-scale pixels are replaced with white if their brightness value is above a chosen threshold, or replaced with black if it is below this value. Because binarized images are highly degraded, pure bottom-up processes typically cannot organize them correctly into their constituent parts, and often one needs to use previously acquired knowledge about objects to identify the objects in them.[24]

The precise nature of this top-down processing is a matter of current research. The particulars of this procedure are not necessary for our purposes. What must be known is that the images we “see” are both based upon the information currently received from the environment and also the information which is constructed by use of pre-existing information.

A Quick Note on Pre-Existing Information

While the schemata applied to construct the imagery we experience is pre-existing, we should also note that even the basic information obtained from the environment is subject to pre-existing information constraints.

A receptor neuron fires on my retina, that information is then passed back to my optic nerve. Some bit of data is processed, a “color”, a “shape”. The colors and shapes which could be constructed must already be existing there in the optic nerve (wherever the actual processing takes places for color and shape).  The color is not in the light, the color is in my processing of the light.  The blue I see in the sky as I sit in my backyard and write is a construction of my brain. That blue must pre-exist the response of a cone on my retina. The firing of the cone merely says, process “blue.” But that “blue” is not out in nature.

This may sound overly “philosophic” or even untrue at present. But by the time we conclude our understanding of sensory perception, you will see the utter strangeness of this problem.

Proof of our observations being construction

If you want proof of the extent to which this imposition upon the world is a manufacture of our sensory system, consider the nature of optical illusions.

I will start with a basic example: Seeing small things as being at a distance is a construction. My anthropology teacher at UCLA had done his field work with pygmies in an African rain forest. He said that when a pygmy was taken from the forest to the edge of the plain, the man would see buffalo at a great distance. Only the pygmy who had spent his entire life never seeing further than say 30 feet away did not see distance: he saw size. The buffalo were not small because they were far away; they were small because they were small.

The distance is not in what we see but in what we know about what see. We have a schemata for distance; the pygmy had none and could not see that distance. It was not a failure of intelligence; it was a failure prior experience.

It has been discovered that the following illusion (among others) is the product of one’s prior experience. Let us consider the Müller-Lyer illusion:

Shape

Description automatically generated with medium confidence

For those reading this essay, the lines on the left (with the flared fins, like the tail of an arrow) will appear longer than the lines on the right (with the pointed fins which appear like an arrowhead). And now to the research:

For decades, vision researchers assumed that the illusion told us something fundamental about human vision. When they showed the illusion to people with normal vision, they were convinced that the line with the inward-pointing arrows would seem longer than the line with outward-pointing arrows. That assumption wasn’t really tested before the 1960s, because until then almost everyone who had seen the illusion was WEIRD—an acronym that cultural psychologists have coined for people from Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, and Democratic societies. In the early 1960s, three researchers remedied that oversight when they showed the illusion to two thousand people from fifteen different cultural groups. The illusion deceived the first few groups. Adults living in Evanston, Illinois, perceived Line B to be on average 20 percent longer than Line A, while students at nearby Northwestern University and white adults in South Africa similarly believed that Line B was between 13 percent and 15 percent longer than Line A. Then the researchers journeyed farther afield, testing people from several African tribes. Bushmen from southern Africa failed to show the illusion at all, perceiving the lines as almost identical in length. Small samples of Suku tribespeople from northern Angola and Bete tribespeople from the Ivory Coast also failed to show the illusion, or saw Line B as only very slightly longer than Line A. Müller-Lyer’s eponymous illusion had deceived thousands of people from WEIRD societies for decades, but it wasn’t universal.[25]

Yet, later research offered a contradictory reading of the evidence. A researcher at Macquarie University when using a computer designed to mimic the human eye was also tricked by the illusion.[26]  This may mean (1) the computer programmer being WEIRD found his bias in the program he created, or (2) people from different places have different physiological functions, or (3) some other process has led to this illusion. While I tend toward answer (1), the fact remains that the illusion has been caused by top-down processing creating the illusion.

Or what Escher’s many illusions:

A picture containing text, black, white

Description automatically generated

You are “seeing” things which cannot exist. Now use your device and take a look at the Charlie Chaplin Illusion: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=QbKw0_v2clo You will see something which simply is not there.

If you would like a popular level explanation of the processing we have been discussing, watch this video: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=m9oTJI9IvuU   At this point, simply take the time to look up “optical illusions”. There are some truly brilliant examples of this. You can check out contest winners here: https://newatlas.com/science/best-optical-illusions-year-2021-contest-winner/

Before we leave this matter of top-down processing, I wish for you to be clear on the extent to which our basic perception of the world is a matter of construction: Our brain does not passively record the world, it actively constructs the world as we experience it.

There are a number of experiments which have shown that the way food and drink tastes can depend upon a number of factors beyond the food itself. An article in Wired magazine cites to these studies (you can find the references linked in the article) which then concludes with this statement:

And this is why the ambience of a restaurant matters. All those rituals of the table are not mere routines. Instead, they help us make sense of the incomplete information coming from the tongue. For instance, when we eat a meal in a fancy place, full of elaborate place settings, fine porcelain and waiters wearing tuxedos, the food is going to taste different than if we ate the same food in a cheap diner. (This helps explain why people spend more money when restaurants play classical music instead of pop tunes.) Because the music matters, but so does everything else. The tongue is easy to dupe.[27]

I wish to stand back and defend the tongue. The tongue has not been tricked in the least: it has done exactly what it was supposed to do. But the tongue is not the last word on taste. The tongue provides some of the information we process as the “taste” of food; but just like our sight, the taste is a construction which uses a limited amount of raw materials from the environment.

Here is the bottom line: The world we experience is not exactly the world as it exists. First, a photon, a movement of air, a chemical wafted to our nose, a food on our tongue, triggers a response in a nerve. That nerve then responds to the environment and sends a message to our brain. Our brain takes that information as well as other information which was not present in that particular response and creates some information which we experience as a sight or sound or taste or tactical quality or scent. That thing we experience is not what is out in the world. What we experience is representation built by our brain.

But we are not nearly done with the problems of our perception of the world.

PSYCHEDELIC DRUGS

In 1938,  a Swiss chemist named Albert Hoffman began experimenting with a  chemical isolated in fungus which grew on rye and was known to cause strange effects on people eating contaminated rye. This fungus is known as ergot.  The chemical which affected the circulatory system was isolated. Thereafter, Hoffman developed a means of synthetically producing this chemical, known as “lysergic acid.” Hoffman then began to experiment:

Using this method, he recreated ergot’s active ingredients as well as novel but similar compounds that, based on the potency of the ergot compounds, could reasonably be expected to have medical uses.

In a sense Hofmann was playing God, combining lysergic acid with various other organic molecules just to see what happened. He created 24 of these lysergic acid combinations. Then he created the 25th, reacting lysergic acid with diethylamine, a derivative of ammonia. The compound was abbreviated as LSD-25 for the purposes of laboratory testing.

https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2014/09/the-accidental-discovery-of-lsd/379564/

Apparently Useless’: The Accidental Discovery of LSD, Tom Shroder, September 9, 2014

In a self-experiment, Hoffman ingested the chemical he created:

Hofmann didn’t discover the drug’s hallucinogenic effects until 1943 when he accidentally ingested a small amount and perceived “extraordinary shapes with intense, kaleidoscopic play of colors.”

Three days later, on April 19, 1943, he took a larger dose of the drug. As Hofmann rode home from work on his bicycle—World War II restrictions made automobile travel off-limits—he experienced the world’s first intentional acid trip[28].

In his first person account of what happened, My Problem Child, Hoffman recounts the effects of this self-experiment as follows:

By now it was already clear to me that LSD had been the cause of the remarkable experience of the previous Friday, for the

altered perceptions were of the same type as before, only much more intense. I

had to struggle to speak intelligibly. I asked my laboratory assistant, who

was informed of the self-experiment, to escort me home. We went by bicycle, no

automobile being available because of wartime restrictions on their use. On

the way home, my condition began to assume threatening forms. Everything in my

field of vision wavered and was distorted as if seen in a curved mirror. I

also had the sensation of being unable to move from the spot. Nevertheless, my

assistant later told me that we had traveled very rapidly. Finally, we arrived

at home safe and sound, and I was just barely capable of asking my companion

to summon our family doctor and request milk from the neighbors.

In spite of my delirious, bewildered condition, I had brief periods of clear

and effective thinking – and chose milk as a nonspecific antidote for

poisoning.

The dizziness and sensation of fainting became so strong at times that I could

no longer hold myself erect, and had to lie down on a sofa. My surroundings

had now transformed themselves in more terrifying ways. Everything in the room

spun around, and the familiar objects and pieces of furniture assumed

grotesque, threatening forrns. They were in continuous motion, animated, as if

driven by an inner restlessness. The lady next door, whom I scarcely

recognized, brought me milk – in the course of the evening I drank more than

two liters. She was no longer Mrs. R., but rather a malevolent, insidious

witch with a colored mask.

Even worse than these demonic transformations of the outer world, were the

alterations that I perceived in myself, in my inner being. Every exertion of

my will, every attempt to put an end to the disintegration of the outer world

and the dissolution of my ego, seemed to be wasted effort. A demon had invaded

me, had taken possession of my body, mind, and soul. I jumped up and screamed,

trying to free myself from him, but then sank down again and lay helpless on

the sofa. The substance, with which I had wanted to experiment, had vanquished

me. It was the demon that scornfully triumphed over my will. I was seized by

the dreadful fear of going insane. I was taken to another world, another

place, another time. My body seemed to be without sensation, lifeless,

strange. Was I dying? Was this the transition? At times I believed myself to

be outside my body, and then perceived clearly, as an outside observer, the

complete tragedy of my situation….[29]

While LSD-25 is perhaps the most “famous” of all psychedelic drugs, having been famous by Harvard psychologist Timothy Leary, it is certainly not the only psychedelic known to human beings. Various psychedelic drugs have been known to produce “mystical” experiences.[30] The English writer Aldus Huxley, having experimented with psychedelics (which were perfectly legal through much of the 20th century), wrote a provocative book entitled, The Doors of Perception. He took the title from a epigram of English poet William Blake, “If the doors of perception were cleansed every thing would appear to man as it is, Infinite. For man has closed himself up, till he sees all things thro’ narrow chinks of his cavern.” (The Marriage of Heaven and Hell).  Huxley’s thesis was that the effect of psychedelic drugs lay behind all “religious” or “mystic experience”:

Reflecting on my experience, I find myself agreeing with the eminent Cambridge philosopher, Dr. C. D. Broad, “that we should do well to consider much more seriously than we have hitherto been inclined to do the type of theory which Bergson put forward in connection with memory and sense perception. The suggestion is that the function of the brain and nervous system and sense organs is in the main eliminative and not productive. Each person is at each moment capable of remembering all that has ever happened to him and of perceiving everything that is happening everywhere in the universe. The function of the brain and nervous system is to protect us from being overwhelmed and confused by this mass of largely useless and irrelevant knowledge, by shutting out most of what we should otherwise perceive or remember at any moment, and leaving only that very small and special selection which is likely to be practically useful.” According to such a theory, each one of us is potentially Mind at Large. But in so far as we are animals, our business is at all costs to survive. To make biological survival possible, Mind at Large has to be funneled through the reducing valve of the brain and nervous system. What comes out at the other end is a measly trickle of the kind of consciousness which will help us to stay alive on the surface of this Particular planet. To formulate and express the contents of this reduced awareness, man has invented and endlessly elaborated those symbol-systems and implicit philosophies which we call languages. Every individual is at once the beneficiary and the victim of the linguistic tradition into which he has been born – the beneficiary inasmuch as language gives access to the accumulated records of other people’s experience, the victim in so far as it confirms him in the belief that reduced awareness is the only awareness and as it bedevils his sense of reality, so that he is all too apt to take his concepts for data, his words for actual things. That which, in the language of religion, is called “this world” is the universe of reduced awareness, expressed, and, as it were, petrified by language.[31]

I know Huxley’s belief that psychedelic drugs stands behind the “experience” of something divine seems a little afield from the thesis of this essay, which is that sensory experience is insufficient to be self-authenticating.  But there is a second-thesis in this essay, namely, that the thesis of sense experience being self-authenticating is a basis upon which we can deny God: I don’t see God in the same way I see a rock, therefore, a rock is more real than God.  My goal in this essay to bring you to understand that sense-experience can only be justified on the thesis of a guarantee of God.

Huxley in a strange way is supportive of my thesis.  The belief that God must be justified as a certain type of sense-experience arose in a particular historical context and was justified on the basis of certain presuppositions of that historical context.  The Enlightenment understanding (to take the idea in a broad fashion), argues that we can merely “subtract” God from our understanding and we can see the world as it actually is. We can see things in motion, we can see things behaving in a regular manner (“laws of nature”). Since things act regularly, and since the only thing which is true is something I can see, God is an unnecessary thesis: (1) I don’t need an agent constantly tinkering; and (2) I don’t see that agent anyway.

But this is actually a philosophy which contains various presuppositions. It is not actually “the way things are.” James K.A. Smith summarizes an argument from Charles Taylor (in A Secular Age) on this point, nicely:

(1) What pretends to be a “discovery” of the ways things are, the “obvious” unveiling of realith once we remove (subtract) myth and enchantment, is in fact a construction, a creation; in short, this wasn’t just a subtraction project. (2) Baseline moral commitments stand behind CWS [“closed world structures”: ideas which exclude the divine], specifically the coming-of-age metaphor of adulthood, having the courage to resist the comforting enchantments of childhood. In short to just “see” the closedness of the immanent frame is to be grown-up.

How (Not) to be Secular, James K.A. Smith, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, Grand Rapids, 2014, p. 99 Taylor explains this “move”  as follows:

[W]hat is being claimed is that some move is being passed off as simple discovery, which in fact is much more like a new construction; a change that involves also a new sense of our identity and our place in the world, with its implicit values, rather than simply registering observable reality[32].

What Huxley’s proves is that the secure sensation of a stable “Enlightenment” world is easily capable of being destabilized by merely a modification of top-down processing (which the psychedelic drug causes)[33]. Those effects include:

Perceptual effects occur along a dose-dependent range from subtle to drastic. The range of different perceptual effects includes perceptual intensification, distortion, illusion, mental imagery, elementary hallucination, and complex hallucination (Klüver, 1928; Kometer and Vollenweider, 2016; Preller and Vollenweider, 2016). Intensifications of color saturation, texture definition, contours, light intensity, sound intensity, timbre variation, and other perceptual characteristics are common (Kometer and Vollenweider, 2016; Kaelen et al., 2018). The external world is experienced as if in higher resolution, seemingly more crisp and detailed, often accompanied by a distinct sense of ‘clarity’ or ‘freshness’ in the environment (Hofmann, 1980; Huxley, 1991; Díaz, 2010; Kometer and Vollenweider, 2016). Sense of meaning in percepts is altered, e.g., ‘Things around me had a new strange meaning for me’ or ‘Objects around me engaged me emotionally much more than usual’ (Studerus et al., 2010).

Perceptual distortions and illusions are extremely common, e.g., ‘Things looked strange’ or ‘My sense of size and space was distorted’ or ‘Edges appeared warped’ or ‘I saw movement in things that weren’t actually moving’ (Dittrich, 1998; Muthukumaraswamy et al., 2013). Textures undulate in rhythmic movements, object boundaries warp and pulsate, and the apparent sizes and shapes of objects can shift rapidly (Kometer and Vollenweider, 2016). Controlled psychophysical studies have measured various alterations in motion perception (Carter et al., 2004), object completion (Kometer et al., 2011), and binocular rivalry (Frecska et al., 2004; Carter et al., 2007).[34]

It is not necessary to detail precisely all that psychedelic-drugs do: that is a matter of current research. Briefly, psychedelic drugs alter the mechanics of top-down processing (citations to resources which discuss this are found in this footnote).[35]

This must be understood: From the perspective of the person experiencing a hallucination, the sensory data being subjectively understood is completely real. When I was a boy, my doctor treated my asthma with a drug named “Marax.” An uncommon, but quite real, side effect of Marax is visual hallucination. I can tell you for a certainty, that the enormous flying ant with bright white wings terrified me. In no sense was that insect not present on the in the doorway to my bedroom. I can still vividly recall the sight of that “nonexistent” insect. The only evidence I had of it being untrue is my father calmly telling me there was no such thing there.

Before we move to the next topic of sensory perception, I want to consider what we have determined: (1) the common “objective” experience of us all is the result of not of naïve seeing “what is there,” but rather the result of a complex process in the brain involving both information from the outside and a deliberate construction of that information into a form. (2) Those forms are affected by our prior history, including cultural exposure. (3) Those forms can create things which cannot actually exist. This is proven by (a) optical illusions, and (b) psychedelic drugs.

No one sees “what is there.” We only see that which our brain constructs in response to neurotransmitters released as a response our neurons on a retina being exposed to photons and having those messages integrated and constructed on the basis of brain structure (which function can be fundamentally altered by drugs) and prior experience.

I wish to further “problematize” the question of our sensory perception by means a further proof of the strangely arbitrary nature of our understand: what happens when you “see sound.”

SYNTHESIA

When I turned 13, I very much wanted to play the piano. My parents were good enough to purchase a piano for me which they could barely afford. I spent entire days doing nothing by banging on the piano our den. What I didn’t know was that the keys on the piano changing colors which waves of colored sound moving up and down the keyboard was an unusual experience. I will tell you that I saw colors moving through the keyboard as I played.  Those colors were “there” every bit as much as the black and white of the keys.

And yet, you likely would not have seen any of these colors. Now, if I saw them, and if they were produced by the act of sound waves striking my ear drum and then being processed by brain, how are they not “real.”  In what sense can you say that hearing a “sound” as the result of moving ear striking my eardrum is “real”, but seeing a “color” is not “real.”

Your sense organs are merely mechanisms to produce some combination of neurotransmitters. A photon here produces this combination, a sound wave there produces a different neurotransmitter combination, and messages are sent hither-and-yon to received and processed.

But to this point, we intuitively think there is a reasonableness, a necessity in our perception. We assume that we “see” light, because it is the nature of light to be seen. We hear sound, because it is appropriate for movements of air to be “heard.” Sounds are what air does; and color is what light does.

If you will recall, above, I said that color does not exist in the light but rather it exists in my brain. Color is something my brain does with a certain signal received by the optic nerve. Color is not in the light; it’s in your brain.

An analogy will help here: If you have ever had the misfortune of installing a combination ceiling fan overhead light, you have my sympathy. It is a miserable task. But it is also a good analogy for what we need to understand about the senses.

Near the door to the room,  somewhere between 4 & 5 feet from the floor is a toggle switch which regulates the flow of electricity to the room. If the switch is “on” electricity will flow past the switch and to whatever device is attached to the wire(s).

When it comes to the overhead fan/light the electricity is distributed separately to the light and to the fan motor. Often additional switches are used to regulate electricity to the light and the motor, separately. If the main switch is “on” and the light switch is “on”, the light will shine. If the motor switch is “on,” the motor will turn the fan. If you turn off the light and leave on the motor, the fan will move and no light will be generated. If you turn off the motor and turn on the light, you will have light and no fan.

The electricity is the same for both the light and the motor. The difference is not in the electricity but what the end of the wire is attached to.  Just to drive this point home, because you will want it to be unstuck in a moment, I will mention a television commercial which asks the question, “How sure are you of your wiring job?” A woman comes into the kitchen and flips the light switch. Her husband has his hand in the garbage disposal. Will the light come on, or will he lose his hand? Same electricity, different result.

Your senses work the same way. The message sent from a rod on your retina does not by necessity need to have the message processed by your optic nerve. Those neurotransmitters could send a message to your olfactory nerve and you could “smell” with your eyes.

Nonsense you say.

But what if were to tell you this actually does happen—usually not retina to olfactory—but it does happen:

Basically, when people experience synesthesia, they can hear colors, smell sounds, and even taste music. And, to add to the complexity, almost every combination of sensory information is possible with synesthesia.1 Here a few of its most common manifestations.

  • Grapheme-Color Synesthesia – Letters and numbers appear with specific colors.
  • Auditory-Tactile Synesthesia – Hearing a sound causes a bodily sensation.
  • Chromesthesia – Certain sounds cause a person to see colors.
  • Lexical-Gustatory Synesthesia – Hearing certain words triggers specific tastes.
  • Mirror-Touch Synesthesia – A person feels (tactile) what another is experiencing.

Interestingly, synesthesia can happen with or without taking drugs.[36]

Since what we perceive is actually the construction of our brain, and since that construction is on the basis of electro-chemical messages, any sense neuron could be paired (theoretically) with any portion of the brain which processes the input of sense neurons.

Here is the bottom-line: there is no inherent correlation between photons and color or shape, between sound waves and sound. That color and light, those sounds, are constructions of the brain.

PERHAPS IT IS ALL A SIMULATION

In 2003 philosopher Nick Bostrom published a paper in The Philosophical Quarterly entitled, “Are We Living in a Computer Simulation?” which article has generated an enormous secondary literature[37].  And while The Matrix reference can be understood readily enough, I wish to underscore a point which follows from the nature of empiricism as complete understanding of consciousness (the “scientism” thesis). 

If the nature of consciousness is nothing more processing electrochemical information, then consciousness is replicable in a computer:

A common assumption in the philosophy of mind is that of substrate- independence. The idea is that mental states can supervene on any of a broad class of physical substrates. Provided a system implements the right sort of computational structures and processes, it can be associated with conscious experiences. It is not an essential property of consciousness that it is implemented on carbon-based biological neural networks inside a cranium: silicon-based processors in a computer could in principle do the trick too.

244. Nothing in scientism can defeat such a thesis.  Indeed, as argued by Fouad Khan in Scientific American  in 2021, consciousness itself is evidence that we are living in a simulation:

Pretty much since the dawn of philosophy we have been asking the question: Why do we need consciousness? What purpose does it serve? Well, the purpose is easy to extrapolate once we concede the simulation hypothesis. Consciousness is an integrated (combining five senses) subjective interface between the self and the rest of the universe. The only reasonable explanation for its existence is that it is there to be an “experience.” That’s its primary raison d’être. Parts of it may or may not provide any kind of evolutionary advantage or other utility. But the sum total of it exists as an experience and hence must have the primary function of being an experience. An experience by itself as a whole is too energy-expensive and information-restrictive to have evolved as an evolutionary advantage. The simplest explanation for the existence of an experience or qualia is that it exists for the purpose of being an experience.

And thus, not only does empiricism not rule-out computer simulated consciousness, it is arguably even the most likely explanation for such.  While the matter will be raised at further length below, it is evident that such an argument is theological. It answers a question well beyond the scope of anything which can seen or heard. It is an answer of ultimate meaning.

DESCARTES DEMON

WHAT WE KNOW ABOUT SENSORY PERCEPTION COMES FROM SENSORY PERCEPTION

There is a peculiar which appears at this point: We have been speaking quite confidentially about the way in which our senses function. We have simultaneously argued (1) there is an arbitrary relationship between light and sight, between moving air and sound; and (2) the perception of which we are conscious is a construction.

Let’s consider some implications of these propositions. First, the nature of shapes and colors does not come from world outside us. The colors and shapes must precede the perception of such shapes and colors. The message sent from our retina merely triggers such colors. The photon cannot create a new color; it can only signal production of a pre-existing color.

Our interaction with the physical world can only result in the production of (new) combinations information which existed prior to the interaction with the environment.

This means we are hardwired (if you will) with a limitation on what we can understand about the world.  This raises the interesting question: What is the source of this information? The sensory system is not built to acquire new information. There is no mechanism to acquire new information.

Second, what we know about sensory perception only comes from the sensory system itself. We can acquire no empirical knowledge around our senses. If our sense are arbitrary and contain such limitations, then how can we know that what we know about sensory system is “true” or complete?

THE LIMITATIONS ON SENSORY PERCEPTION

There is just one further aspect of sensory perception which we must consider: We don’t know what we don’t know. Until recently, we were unaware that the same waves which deliver visible light deliver infrared and ultraviolet “light.” Beyond these lie x-rays and radio waves.  Bats hear sounds we cannot hear. Bloodhounds track scents we cannot smell. And so, there lies a world beyond our senses.

We have overcome such limitations by developing technology to extend our senses. We track these colors and sounds and the translate the information into some sense which makes sense to us. An infrared photograph of the sun is translated into a visible (false color) photograph. Such a translation provides us some, albeit incomplete, knowledge of that world.

But there is a greater problem. Since our senses are developed to only respond to a narrow range of potential attributes of the “real world” (whatever that might be), there could any number of things which are attributes of that world; attributes which are unknown and unknowable:

It is readily allowed, that other beings may possess many senses of which we can have no conception; because the ideas of them have never been introduced to us, in the only manner, by which an idea can have access to the mind, to wit, by the actual feeling and sensation[38].

This leads to the very real possibility that the world is mostly unknown and unknowable:

The world is mostly unknown. This statement immediately emphasizes the point that we are not conscious of most of the environmental events that occur around us. The world consists of stimuli of which we may or may not be aware. These stimuli are pressure variations, chemicals, electromagnetic radiation, temperature, and even gravity.[39]

EMPRICISM IS A TRICKY FOUNDATION

The prestige of “modern, modern science” (to use Schaffer’s apt phrase)[40] lies in the self-authenticating claim of empiricism.  But as we can see, empiricism does not provide self-authentication.  It provides an arbitrary construction which is limited in ways we cannot even imagine. Indeed, empiricism may lead to the conclusion that what we perceive has been programmed by another. There is no “real world” to which have access.

Empiricism left to itself creates an epistemological trap from which we cannot escape. It cannot justify what we “know.” While we can be certain (at least in a sense used by Descartes) that we know what we know, we do not know what it is that we know. Empiricism leaves us trapped in our brain with no way out.

Indeed, it is difficult to know how empiricism can justify something beyond solipsism (which is merely a correlative of the computer simulation theory).  It seems that if we are left with empiricism alone the best we can do is either (1) just ignore the problem, or (2) resign ourselves to an extreme form of skepticism such as belief that all life is illusory.

I am not saying that an atheist scientist who denies anything beyond the functioning of his brain and insists, without justification, that this sensation is self-authenticating knows nothing of the real world.  Common grace is sufficient to provide a basis for some knowledge even without an adequate justification for the belief in the truthfulness of such knowledge.

But problem with meaning remains. This will be examined more in the next essay which will begin to address the question of “reason” when it comes to knowledge based upon sense perception (recall the thumbnail definition of science as empiricism and reason).

To set up that further consideration, I hope for you to understand the following: A fact “means” something based upon its relationship to some larger matrix of knowledge. If you are holding a baseball and start to throw it but stop, you have committed a “balk” if you are playing a game of baseball: that is what you stopped motion “means”.  If you are in a park with your dog, the stopped motion “means” something quite different. If you are alone in your backyard, it has a third “meaning.” The word “gift” means poison in Germany and a pleasant surprise in Germantown, Pennsylvania.

What these sense perceptions “mean” depends upon the context in which we understand them to take place. I have attempted to outline the nature of our sensory apparatus based upon our observations of that sensory apparatus.  If we understand these sensations developed in our brain as a matter of accumulated solutions to survival problems arrived at over millions of years, they have a particular meaning. If we understand these same sensations as the product of an apparatus designed by a loving Creator who intends for us to understand something of the Creator, the sensations have a different meaning.

The nature of the “meaning” when applied to sensations can be largely overlooked if one is a chemist, say. But when it comes to psychology, the question meaning is critical. As noted above, psychology holds a unique place as a “science” which claims to tell us how we know. The full implications of that claim will be developed as we continue our examination. But that question of meaning begins here when the photon sets off a series of electrical and chemical responses.

And it is to this point which I have aimed from the beginning. The greater claim of “psychology” is that it is scientific and based upon self-authenticating empiricism and reason.  We have not considered reason, but we have seen that empiricism won’t answer to the demand made upon it.

To put a theological point on the problem, seeking to rely upon such an understanding of  “science” is idolatry:

To justify our knowledge we must presuppose that (1) there is an appropriate correlation between light and sight (sense and perception); (2) the pre-existing information used to develop perceptions is appropriate; (3) what we have access to is sufficient; (4) what we know is “true.”

Someone with sufficient power and moral goodness outside us and before us alone can guarantee such knowledge. This is not a sufficient argument to contend that such a God must exist. But what this argument does require is that one cannot assert any nonsense that knowledge of the world or others can be had without such a God.

The manner in which understand basic sensation, the meaning we assign to such sensation will frame the remainder of analysis of psychology. As you can see, I propose that understanding sensation as an arbitrary process of our brain (which must be the conclusion of one how seeks to authenticate sensation on the basis of sensation) creates a level of incoherence in our understanding of human beings; and certainly creates a trouble at the most basic level of our science.

Since we all must begin with some presuppositions with themselves are not subject to analysis, I will begin the basic Christian propositions that our understanding must be informed by our text.

THE HEAVENS DECLARE

The dead end of empiricism certainly must be rejected on any Christian reading. Paul, in Romans 1, contends that we are held morally and eternally accountable to what we perceive:

18 For the wrath of God is revealed from heaven against all ungodliness and unrighteousness of men, who by their unrighteousness suppress the truth. 19 For what can be known about God is plain to them, because God has shown it to them. 20 For his invisible attributes, namely, his eternal power and divine nature, have been clearly perceived, ever since the creation of the world, in the things that have been made. So they are without excuse. 21 For although they knew God, they did not honor him as God or give thanks to him, but they became futile in their thinking, and their foolish hearts were darkened. 22 Claiming to be wise, they became fools, 23 and exchanged the glory of the immortal God for images resembling mortal man and birds and animals and creeping things.

24 Therefore God gave them up in the lusts of their hearts to impurity, to the dishonoring of their bodies among themselves, 25 because they exchanged the truth about God for a lie and worshiped and served the creature rather than the Creator, who is blessed forever! Amen.

Romans 1:18–25 (ESV) Paul here is laying an extraordinary burden upon our perception of the physical world. What is disclosed in the physical world and which is then realized through our senses is the basis upon which God will impose eternal judgment. Look at those words which end verse 21, “So they are without excuse.”  That is a dumbfounding sentence.

As we have seen, the senses, on their own terms, are a mechanism which transform interactions with the environment (whatever it is) into some “perception” fixed in our brain (I am leaving the issue of mind to the side). The relationship between the initial contact with the environment and the realized sensation is a construction (top-down processing), arbitrary (as demonstrated by synthesia), and incomplete in some unknowable manner. It cannot authenticate the source of its own knowledge. And yet God will hold us eternally accountable for the same.

One corollary of this proposition, is that we must understand our sensory apparatus to be more than adequate: it provides us exactly as much information as God deems it minimally necessary. It must be “true” knowledge in a critical sense, because God will judge us on this knowledge. In short, Christianity provides a guarantee, a justification for believing the content of our sense perception.  Calvin’s comment here is interesting for our purposes:

By saying, that God has made it manifest, he means, that man was created to be a spectator of this formed world, and that eyes were given him, that he might, by looking on so beautiful a picture, be led up to the Author himself[41].

Consider those words, “Man was created to be a spectator of this formed world.” Our capacity to perceive the world is in part a reason for which we were created.  Our sensory apparatus is not merely adequate, it is necessary for our purpose in existing.  At this point, I want you to consider the argument, above, made in connection with computer simulation: our conscious, having no survival purpose, can best be explained on the basis of living in a simulation. Calvin, relying upon Paul, says, our sensation and conscious awareness of that sensation is best explained on the basis that we were created to be spectators in the theater of God’s glory.

The knowledge we obtain in this theater should lead to a theological understaning of the world:

But just what does Paul mean when he claims that human beings “see” and “understand” from creation and history that a powerful God exists? Some think that Paul is asserting only that people have around them the evidence of God’s existence and basic qualities; whether people actually perceive it or become personally conscious of it is not clear. But Paul’s wording suggests more than this. He asserts that people actually come to “understand” something about God’s existence and nature. How universal is this perception? The flow of Paul’s argument makes any limitation impossible. Those who perceive the attributes of God in creation must be the same as those who suppress the truth in unrighteousness and are therefore liable to the wrath of God. Paul makes clear that this includes all people (see 3:9, 19–20)[42].

You can begin to understand the importance of putting our sensory perception into a theological framework. We are not just observing this and that for the purpose of not dying. We are observing for the purpose of coming to know God.  This is the reason why the Psalmist says the world is declaring God:

            1           The heavens declare the glory of God,

and the sky above proclaims his handiwork.

            2           Day to day pours out speech,

and night to night reveals knowledge.

            3           There is no speech, nor are there words,

whose voice is not heard.

            4           Their voice goes out through all the earth,

and their words to the end of the world.

                        In them he has set a tent for the sun,

            5           which comes out like a bridegroom leaving his chamber,

and, like a strong man, runs its course with joy.

            6           Its rising is from the end of the heavens,

and its circuit to the end of them,

and there is nothing hidden from its heat.

Psalm 19:1–6 (ESV) The world, to use Calvin’s language, is a theater in which we are to observe the glory of God:

Therefore, because God has put us in this world as in a theatre, to contemplate his glory, let us acknowledge him to be such as he declares himself to us, and because he gives us the second instruction which is even more familiar in his word, let us be more confident and stirred with a burning zeal to aspire unto him until we reach that goal, and let us be aware that this world was created for that purpose and that our Lord has placed us here and has favored us with living here and enjoying all the things he has created.

Now, the sun was not made for itself and is even a creature without feeling. The trees, the each, which produces food for us — all of that works for man. The animals, although they move and have some feeling, do not do for all that have this high capacity to understand what belongs to God, for they do not discriminate between good and evil. We also see that their life and death are for men’s use and service[43].

This means that we should understand epistemology, a theory for knowing what we know and why, as doxological. An understanding of knowledge which does not lead to a deeper understanding of the glory of God is faulty at its core.

This presents an interesting problem: we cannot justify the content of sense experience on the basis of that sense experience; and simultaneously, we make ultimate claims which are grounded (at least in part) in sense experience. This leaves us with a theological problem.


[1] https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=cHxGUe1cjzM

[2] I am well aware that “psychology” is in practice an almost undefinable term. There are so many different schools of thought and such a wide array of fields, that the term is close to meaningless. For purposes of my examination, I am limiting my concerns in this essay to the sort of “scientific” work which is conducted at a university involving experiments and observations and theories which more or less match the procedures of a hard science. This particular essay which will focus primarily upon sensory perception will consider matter more in the line of physiology than Freud.

[3] https://dictionary.cambridge.org/us/dictionary/english/physics

[4] “Math professor claims equation 2+2=4 ‘reeks of white supremacist patriarchy’”

by Emma Colton, Social Media Editor |   | August 10, 2020 11:00 AM

Washington Times, https://www.washingtonexaminer.com/news/math-professor-claims-equation-2-2-4-reeks-of-white-supremacist-patriarchy

[5] See for example, https://www.foxnews.com/media/lia-thomas-new-york-times-science-reporter-anatomical-chromosomal-hormonal-scrutiny

February 18, 2022 10:37pm EST

Lia Thomas: NYT science reporter mocked for claiming transgender swimmer faces ‘hormonal scrutiny’

Joseph A. Wulfsohn

[6] The Ironies of Strong and Weak Scientism

Posted by: J.P. Moreland

September 27, 2018

The Ironies of Strong and Weak Scientism

[7] This entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy nicely introduces this man: entry “Willard Van Orman Quine” https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/quine/

[8] https://as.nyu.edu/content/dam/nyu-as/philosophy/documents/faculty-documents/foley/Foley_Quine-Naturalized.pdf   p. 245(3)

[9] I have heard it said that science is a mnemonic device: it is simply a collection of recollections: when I saw this, I next saw that.

[10] There is a great deal to be said by the methodology of science; but at this point a general understanding will suffice.

[11]

 It is evident, that all reasonings from causes or effects terminate in conclusions, concerning matter of fact; that is, concerning the existence of objects or of their qualities. It is also evident, that the idea, of existence is nothing different from the idea of any object, and that when after the simple conception of any thing we would conceive it as existent, we in reality make no addition to or alteration on our first idea. Thus when we affirm, that God is existent, we simply form the idea of such a being, as he is represented to us; nor is the existence, which we attribute to him, conceived by a particular idea, which we join to the idea of his other qualities, and can again separate and distinguish from them. But

A Treatise of Human Nature (p. 69). Kindle Edition. Part I, sect. VII

[12] https://electronics.howstuffworks.com/film3.htm Charles Woodworth, How Photographic Film Works March 12, 2022

[13] http://edit.educ.ttu.edu/site/jcheon/manual/Digital_Photography.pdf , Basic Photography Using a Digital Camera, Jong Pil Cheon, accessed

[14] Piper M. Treuting, Rachel Wong, Daniel C. Tu, Isabella Phan,

21 – Special Senses: Eye,

Editor(s): Piper M. Treuting, Suzanne M. Dintzis,

Comparative Anatomy and Histology,

Academic Press,

2012,

Pages 395

[15] http://webhome.phy.duke.edu/~hsg/264L/images/photons-on-retina.html

“Mammalia retinas can respond to single photons” no author.

[16] Ibid.

[17] http://hyperphysics.phy-astr.gsu.edu/hbase/vision/rodcone.html

[18] https://www.hms.harvard.edu/bss/neuro/bornlab/nb204/papers2006/Masland_Lecture2_handout.doc

[19] https://www.hms.harvard.edu/bss/neuro/bornlab/nb204/papers2006/Masland_Lecture2_handout.doc

[20] Perception Lecture Notes: LGN and V1, Professor David Heeger, https://www.cns.nyu.edu/~david/courses/perception/lecturenotes/V1/lgn-V1.html

[21] LGN slides, Aditi Majumder, https://www.ics.uci.edu/~majumder/vispercep/chap3_LGN_highvision.pdf

[22] https://qbi.uq.edu.au/brain/brain-functions/visual-perception

The Univeristy of Queensland Queensland Brain Institute

Visual Perception

[23] Top-down influences on visual processing

Charles D. Gilbert1 and Wu Li2

Nat Rev Neurosci. Author manuscript; available in PMC 2013 Dec 16.

Published in final edited form as:

Nat Rev Neurosci. 2013 May; 14(5): 10.1038/nrn3476.

Published online 2013 Apr 18. doi: 10.1038/nrn3476

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3864796/

[24] 24

Multiple Mechanisms of Top Down Processing in Vision Giorgio Gannis, Stephen M. Klosslyn

Publisher Name

Springer, Tokyo 2007

Editors

Shintaro Funahashi

[25]

[26]

[27] https://www.wired.com/2011/11/does-music-make-wine-taste-better/

Does Music Change The Taste Of Wine? Jonah Lerner

Nov. 2, 2011, https://www.wired.com/2011/11/does-music-make-wine-taste-better/

[28] LSD, June 14, 2017

Citation:

Article Title

LSD

Author

History.com Editors

Website Name

HISTORY

URL

https://www.history.com/topics/crime/history-of-lsd

Access Date

March 31, 2022

[29] Albert Hoffman, My Problem Child, trans. Jonathan Ott, found at https://www.cs.cmu.edu/~ehn/release/problem-child.html

[30] https://psychedelicreview.com/mystical-encounters-with-and-without-drugs/

Mystical Encounters, With and Without Drugs

APRIL 27, 2021 – BY ABIGAIL E. CALDER, MSC

March 31, 2022

https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2013/12/religion-as-a-product-of-psychotropic-drug-use/282484/

Richard J. Miller

Religion as a Product Psychotropic Drug Use

December 27, 2012

https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2013/12/religion-as-a-product-of-psychotropic-drug-use/282484/

The notion that hallucinogenic drugs played a significant part in the development of religion has been extensively discussed, particularly since the middle of the twentieth century. Various ideas of this type have been collected into what has become known as the entheogen theory. The word entheogen is a neologism coined in 1979 by a group of ethnobotanists (those that study the relationship between people and plants). The literal meaning of entheogen is “that which causes God to be within an individual” and might be considered as a more accurate and academic term for popular terms such as hallucinogen or psychedelic drug. By the term entheogen we understand the use of psychoactive substances for religious or spiritual reasons rather than for purely recreational purposes.

[31] Aldus Huxley, The Doors of Perception, online at http://www.ignaciodarnaude.com/espiritualismo/Huxley,Doors%20of%20Perception.pdf

p. 6

[32] Charles Taylor, A Secular Age, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 2007, 565.

[33] Perception is in the Details:

A Predictive Coding Account of the Psychedelic Phenomenon

Sarit Pink-Hashkes (S.PinkHashkes@student.ru.nl)

Radboud University, Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition, and Behaviour, PO Box 9104, 6500 HE Nijmegen, The Netherlands

Iris van Rooij (i.vanrooij@donders.ru.nl)

Radboud University, Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition, and Behaviour, PO Box 9104, 6500 HE Nijmegen, The Netherlands

Johan Kwisthout (j.kwisthout@donders.ru.nl)

Click to access paper0550.pdf

[34] “Unifying Theories of Psychedelic Drug Effects”

Frontiers in Pharmacology, 2018; 9: 172.

Published online 2018 Mar 2. doi: 10.3389/fphar.2018.00172

Link R. Swanson

[35] John Hopkins Medical

June 5, 2020

How psychedelic drug psilocybin works on brain

https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2020/06/200605121512.htm

“Unifying Theories of Psychedelic Drug Effects”

Frontiers in Pharmacology, 2018; 9: 172.

Published online 2018 Mar 2. doi: 10.3389/fphar.2018.00172

Link R. Swanson

LSD and the Anarchic Brain

LSD flattens the brain’s functional hierarchy and energy landscape via 5-HT2A

JUNE 10, 2021 – BY GEORGE BLACKBURNE

LSD and the Anarchic Brain

Whole-Body Effects of Psychedelics – Part 1

How do psychedelics interact with the human body beyond brain cells?

JUNE 15, 2021 – BY JOSE ALEXANDRE SALERNO, MS

Whole-Body Effects of Psychedelics – Part 1

Whole-Body Effects of Psychedelics Part 2 – Blood and Immune System

The journey of psychedelics through the bloodstream and their interaction with the available serotonin receptors along the way.

AUGUST 17, 2021 – BY JOSE ALEXANDRE SALERNO, MS

Whole-Body Effects of Psychedelics Part 2 – Blood and Immune System

Editor’s Choice Award 2021-Best Study on Psychedelics and Neuroplasticity

DECEMBER 14, 2021 – BY BARBARA E. BAUER, MS

Editor’s Choice Award 2021-Best Study on Psychedelics and Neuroplasticity

[36] Psychedelic Synesthesia: Smell That Tune

Intertwining of the senses creates some mind-blowing experiences.

MARCH 22, 2021 – BY BARBARA E. BAUER, MS

Psychedelic Synesthesia: Smell That Tune

[37] Nick Bostrom

The Philosophical Quarterly, Volume 53, Issue 211, April 2003, Pages 243–255,

[38] p. 15

OXFORD WORLD’S CLASSICS

DAVID HUME

An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding

Edited with an Introduction and Notes by

PETER MILLICAN

Oxford University Press, Oxford. 2007

Click to access hume_enquiry.pdf

[39] David R Soderquist. Sensory Processes. SAGE Publications, Inc, 2002.

Thousand Oaks, California

p.1

[40] The early scientists believed in the uniformity of natural causes. What they did not believe in was the uniformity of natural causes in a closed system. That little phrase makes all the difference in the world. It makes the difference between natural science and a science that is rooted in naturalistic philosophy. It makes all the difference between what I would call modern science and what I would call modern modern science. It is important to notice that this is not a failing of science as science, but rather that the uniformity of natural causes in a closed system has become the dominant philosophy among scientists.

Francis A. Schaeffer, The Complete Works of Francis A. Schaeffer: A Christian Worldview, vol. 1 (Westchester, IL: Crossway Books, 1982), 229–230.

[41] John Calvin, Romans, electronic ed., Calvin’s Commentaries (Albany, OR: Ages Software, 1998), Ro 1:19.

[42] Douglas J. Moo, The Epistle to the Romans, The New International Commentary on the New Testament (Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1996), 105.

[43] Jean Calvin, “The Triune God at Work (Gen. 1:1-2)” in Sermons On Genesis, Chapters 1:1-11:4: Forty-Nine Sermons Delivered in Geneva between 4 September 1559 and 23 January 1560, trans. Rob Roy McGregor (Edinburgh: Banner of Truth Trust, ©2009), 6.

Augustine on refusing to see truth

03 Wednesday Jun 2020

Posted by memoirandremains in Augustine

≈ Leave a comment

Tags

Augustine, epistemology, Noetic Effect

“Unfortunately, however, there prevails a major and malignant malady of fools, the victims of which mistake their irrational impulses for truth and reason, even when confronted with as much evidence as any man has a right to expect from another. It may be an excess of blindness which prevents them from seeing the most glaring facts, or a perverse obstinacy which prevents them from”

City of God

Book II, chap 1

Carl F. Henry, Ways of Knowing.5

11 Tuesday Oct 2016

Posted by memoirandremains in Carl F Henry, Church History, Epistemology, Uncategorized

≈ Leave a comment

Tags

Carl F Henry, Church History, epistemology, God Revelation and Authority, Schleiermacher, The Ways of Knowing

The previous post on Henry’s essay, “Ways of Knowing” can be found here.

In the next section of the essay, Henry considers Experience as the basis for knowledge.

Empiricism: Empiricism relies upon the senses rather than upon intuition. However, that simple concept has undergone significant development over history.

Mystics: Mystics argue that their experiences should not be ruled out of court merely because they are not shared by all. However, in contemporary philosophy only objective sense information constitutes an acceptable experience to consider.

Aristotle/Thomas and Modern Empiricism: Aristotle and Thomas considered empiricism as a first step: “perceptual induction”can then lead to propositions upon which one can build. Thomas famously developed proofs for God based upon empirical perception of the world without resort to revelation.

Modern empiricism could not tolerate such a thing:

The special interest of empiricism, moreover, is to identify events for the sake of the prediction and control of perceptual experience, rather than to render them comprehensively intelligible in relation to metaphysical reality (cf. Edwin A. Burtt, Types of Religious Philosophy, pp. 197 ff.).

Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation, and Authority, vol. 1 (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999), 79.

Applied to Theology:  Hume attacked the Thomistic proposition that one could move from empirical observation to proof of God:

Thomistic contention that the existence of God, and the existence and immortality of the soul, are logically demonstrable simply through empirical considerations independent of divine revelation.1 Hume’s contention was that those who profess theological beliefs on empirical grounds have no right to such beliefs unless they produce requisite perceptual evidence, and that in the absence of demonstrative empirical proof, belief is unreasonable.

Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation, and Authority, vol. 1 (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999), 79–80.

Henry then draws an interesting line between Hume and Schleiermacher: Schleiermacher expanded the scope of empirical data to “religious consciousness” rather than mere cognition. He grounded Christianity in the human experience — thus attempting to rescue  knowledge of God from Humean skepticism but at the cost of a supernatural Christianity:

Schleiermacher boldly identified the empirical method as adequate to deal with religious concerns and decisive for the fortunes of Christianity, yet he sought at the same time to broaden the definition of empiricism so that—contrary to Hume’s skeptical analysis of theological claims—an appeal to the religious consciousness could yield a positive and constructive verdict. Schleiermacher considered feeling rather than cognition the locus of religious experience, and he applied the empirical method hopefully to the claims of Christian theism. Rejecting the historic evangelical emphasis that the truth of revelation rests on an authority higher than science, Schleiermacher broke with miraculous Christianity and held that all events must conform to empirically verifiable law.

Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation, and Authority, vol. 1 (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999), 80.

This trajectory leaves open the development of a completely new religion still calling itself “Christianity” without maintaining the same revelatory content (which has happened in great deal in the West).

As Henry notes, what sort of rationale can ground one’s claim of “religious experience” or “truth”. Even empiricism generally can be of little use beyond analysis of material objects:  “But how does one arrive at a permanently valid ought, at fixed norms of any kind, by the empirical method of knowing?” (P. 83) That of course has not stopped many from claiming an absolute authority for empiricism.

It does boast engineering feats, but such feats do not prove or disprove anything with respect to God. One can simply cannot argue from “I made a bridge” to “There is no God.” As Henry explains:

Taken by itself, the empirical method provides no basis for affirming or denying supernatural realities, since by definition it is a method for dealing only with perceptible realities. It cannot, therefore, validate supraperceptible being; nor can it validate moral norms either or confirm past historical events in present public experience. The empiricist must acknowledge that his method leads finally to one of many possible views, and not to final certainty about anything.

Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation, and Authority, vol. 1 (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999), 85.

 

 

Carl F. Henry: Ways of Knowing (2)

22 Wednesday Jun 2016

Posted by memoirandremains in Apologetics, Carl F Henry, John Calvin, Uncategorized

≈ Leave a comment

Tags

Alvin Plantinga, Apologetics, Brian Morley, epistemology, Intuition, John Calvin, knowledge

Portrait of John Calvin

John Calvin

Intuition 2:  Rational Intuition

Rather than thinking of intuition as a non-rational, it is possible to consider intuition as consisting of some sort of information which we just know:

Those who espouse rational intuition insist that human beings know certain propositions are immediately to be true, without resort to inference; in other words, that all men possess certain underived a priori truths without any process of inference whereby these truths are derived. Rational intuition must therefore be clearly distinguished from mystical intuition.

Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation, and Authority, vol. 1 (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999), 74. This a position which Christian thinkers have often advanced. For example, John Calvin argues that human beings have an intuitive sense of the divine:

There is within the human mind, and indeed by natural instinct, an awareness of divinity. This we take to be beyond controversy. To prevent anyone from taking refuge in the pretense of ignorance, God himself has implanted bin all men a certain understanding of his divine majesty. Ever renewing its memory, he repeatedly sheds fresh drops Since, therefore, men one and all perceive that there is a God and that he is their Maker, they are condemned by their own testimony because they have failed to honor him and to consecrate their lives to his will. If ignorance of God is to be looked for anywhere, surely one is most likely to find an example of it among the more backward folk and those more remote from civilization. Yet there is, as the eminent pagan says, no nation so barbarous, no people so savage, that they have not a deep-seated conviction that there is a God

John Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion 1 & 2, ed. John T. McNeill, trans. Ford Lewis Battles, vol. 1, The Library of Christian Classics (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2011), 43–44. A similar position is advocated by Alvin Plantiga:

A major thrust of his early apologetic work was to show that Christian belief can be rational even if unsupported by traditional evidence, there being in his view no adequate, noncircular arguments to had for belief in God. Yet he has never regarded faith as a fideistic leap. Rather, it is a kind of knowledge that can be had immediately because of the way we are created and cthe action of the Holy Spirit, producting in us what Calvin called the sensus divinatatus – an intellectually grounded by noninferential awareness of the divine ….

Brian K. Morley, Mapping Apologetics (Downers Grove: IVP Academic, 2015), 119. (As for apologetics, this is a unique book. It explains the nature of the various apologetic schools, there relationships to one-another; together with critiques and praises. I don’t know of any book like it. I work with Dr. Morley (and he even gave me my copy of the book – full disclosure), but I could not more highly recommend the book. I used it with my graduate students.)

Carl F. Henry: Ways of Knowing

22 Wednesday Jun 2016

Posted by memoirandremains in Carl F Henry, Philosophy, Psychology, Uncategorized

≈ Leave a comment

Tags

Carl F Henry, epistemology, knowledge, Mysticism, Philosophy, Psychology

14751511452_e937c3943f_o

This chapter is an overview and critique of the various philosophical positions asserted as to how human beings know. Henry arranges the schools as Intuition, Experience & Reason. Henry particularly concerns himself with the way in which a human can know, or claim to know (or why one cannot know) God.

Intuition, Part One

Henry divides the various schools of “intuition” into four. The first is the non-rational immediate experience of the impersonal divine. The claim:

That religious reality is known not by sense observation or by philosophical reasoning but by intuition or immediate apprehension has been asserted by various thinkers who insist that God is to be found in one’s own inner experience as an instant awareness of the religious Ultimate

Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation, and Authority, vol. 1 (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999), 70.

The mystic intuition claims that God cannot be understood in any manner which applies in “daily life”. God even “transcends distinctions of truth and falsehood, and is beyond good and evil” (Id. at 71).  Therefore, the mystic’s experience cannot be verified in any way applies to other knowledge.

This leads to the obvious objection: If we cannot judge the mystic’s “experience” of God, can we may any evaluation of the claim at all? Indeed, how can we judge anything: “What criterion of truth and error remains if God is beyond truth?” (Ibid.)

Moreover, how can we make any determination as to the mystic’s claim to knowledge. If the experience cannot be related in any manner at all, what can any other do with the claim? The mystic’s paradoxical language about God is not subject to any sort of evaluation by any other person.

The mystic’s experiences may be of psychological interest, but they cannot afford a basis for another person to enter into that knowledge.

This intutionist knowledge is the basis of Protestant Liberalism, as founded by Schleiermacher:

Friedrich Schleiermacher—contended that contact with ultimate reality is to be made not intellectually or conceptually but intuitionally, mystically, immediately. The Absolute is to be felt, not conceived. As a result, these men wrote not of God as the Religious Object, but of their own religious sentiments. Schleiermacher, founder of Protestant liberalism, in effect substituted the psychology of religious experience for theology, or the science of God.

Id at p. 72.

Making the subject of God the question of religious sentiment is “implicitly pantheistic” (Id. at p 73). There is no distinguishable person there, just my inarticulate apprehension of some-thing (not some-one).

Pantheism is inherently without moral categories, because there is only what is & my psychological reaction to it. There is no good or evil in such a world.

This, of course, is completely the opposite of the Biblical assertion that God has made himself know rationally, understandably. God is other, but God has also mediated knowledge of himself through the Logos, the Son has made the Father known.

While there is occasionally talk of “Christian mysticism”, it certainly cannot mean this sort of a-rational, incommunicable experience which loses all sense of “I and thou”, Creator-Creation. The talk of Union with Christ does not entail absorption into any infinite:

The Bible nowhere accommodates the speculative notion that ontological disjunction from the Divine is the central human problem, to be overcome by man’s pursuit of ecstatic union with the Ineffable; rather, the basic problem is that of overcoming man’s moral alienation from his Maker, and a revelation and atonement that God himself provides opens the way to the restoration of spiritual fellowship

Id. at pp. 73–74.

We Murder to Dissect

28 Tuesday May 2013

Posted by memoirandremains in Epistemology, John Frame

≈ Leave a comment

Tags

Duchess, epistemology, John Frame, poem, Poetry, The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God, The Tables Turned, Theory, Wallace Stevens, William Wordsworth

We Murder to Dissect

John Frame begins his volume The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God with the observation that knowledge depends upon its object:  what we can know, how we can know differs with the object of knowledge. For example, today I read story of a “photograph” of a hydrogen atom. That photograph provided a kind of knowledge obtained in a specific manner. Such knowledge is true – but it is not comprehensive. Moreover such knowledge differs fundamentally from the knowledge I have of my family members.

Even the barest consider will demonstrate his point, “Our criteria, methods and goals in knowledge all depend on what we seek to know” (9).

To confuse the appropriate form of knowledge for a particular object would be to miss the object altogether. Wordsworth drew this out in his poem, “The Tables Turned”:

         UP! up! my Friend, and quit your books;

          Or surely you’ll grow double:

          Up! up! my Friend, and clear your looks;

          Why all this toil and trouble?

 

          The sun, above the mountain’s head,

          A freshening lustre mellow

          Through all the long green fields has spread,

          His first sweet evening yellow.

 

          Books! ’tis a dull and endless strife:

          Come, hear the woodland linnet,                             10

          How sweet his music! on my life,

          There’s more of wisdom in it.

 

The ‘friend’ who seeks nature in his books – in scientific study, if you will – will miss the beauty and wonder of nature in his study of nature.  Wordsworth contends that the friend has brought the wrong means to study the object. Thus, in “studying” the friend misses everything of importance – in fact he destroys the object in his search:

          Sweet is the lore which Nature brings;

          Our meddling intellect

          Mis-shapes the beauteous forms of things:–

          We murder to dissect.

 

          Enough of Science and of Art;

          Close up those barren leaves;                               30

          Come forth, and bring with you a heart

          That watches and receives.

 

This same principle applies to theology, “Knowing God is something utterly unique, since God himself is unique” (9).  Much of the argument about God hinges upon this plain proposition: God is not known the way knows the batting average of a baseball player; a wife cannot be known the way one knows a spider. God cannot be known the way one knows types of coffee. And yet, we often grow frustrated with a personal God who will only be known personally.

Now God – as all things and all persons – is not and cannot be known absent the knowledge of other objects.  God is known in his relationship to his creation – just as a child is known in relationship to a parent: the relationship is a fundamental aspect of the knowledge[1]. 

This implies a much broader understanding of knowledge, “So we cannot know God without knowing other things at the same time”. We cannot know God as Creator without knowing (in some manner) creation. [2] Now this problem of knowledge of God becomes all the greater when we think that we are within the scope of God’s creation – there is not some unbiased place from which to observe. It is as if one seeks to know about a person, but only after the relationship is established – as a child has no potential space to know the parent except from the vantage of being a child.


[1] Wallace Stevens gets at some of this in his poem “Theory:

I am what is around me.

Women understand this.
One is not duchess
A hundred yards from a carriage.

These, then are portraits:
A black vestibule;
A high bed sheltered by curtains.

These are merely instances.

[2] Wallace Steven’s poem, “Theory” illustrates this fact of relatoin

Categories

Archives

Recent Posts

  • Thomas Traherne, The Soul’s Communion with her Savior. 1.1.6
  • Thinking About Meaning While Weeding the Garden
  • Thomas Traherne, The Soul’s Communion With Her Savior 1.1.6
  • Addressing Loneliness
  • Brief in Chiles v Salazar

Categories

Archives

Recent Posts

  • Thomas Traherne, The Soul’s Communion with her Savior. 1.1.6
  • Thinking About Meaning While Weeding the Garden
  • Thomas Traherne, The Soul’s Communion With Her Savior 1.1.6
  • Addressing Loneliness
  • Brief in Chiles v Salazar

Blog at WordPress.com.

  • Follow Following
    • memoirandremains
    • Join 630 other followers
    • Already have a WordPress.com account? Log in now.
    • memoirandremains
    • Customize
    • Follow Following
    • Sign up
    • Log in
    • Report this content
    • View site in Reader
    • Manage subscriptions
    • Collapse this bar
 

Loading Comments...